Kripke's Meaning Skepticism 1

  Рет қаралды 10,123

Kane B

Kane B

Күн бұрын

Пікірлер: 49
@cliffordhodge1449
@cliffordhodge1449 7 жыл бұрын
The deep problem illustrated is not merely that symbols/language pose a problem or that memory poses a problem, etc. It is this: mathematical functions are functions. What is a function? It is the mapping of members of one set onto those of another set. Is there one set rule dictating what may or may not be stipulated as a function? No. In a given case the briefest and most efficient piossible way of stating the rule for the function may be nothing less than an exhaustive listing which states for each member of the first set which member it is mapped onto in the second set. That seems like a lousy sort of set, but that does not prevent it from existing or being stipulated. And any function defined by a few iterations followed by, "and so on in similar fashion", clearly does not tell you what "similar fashion" is, so the limited iteration does not logically imply anything about what you should do with the next member mapping. This, by the way, is an idea which I think can be applied to the problem of the cultural relativity of intelligence test questions which often follow a function which implicity looks for the answer which would be most popular among some unspecified group.
@justus4684
@justus4684 2 жыл бұрын
4:19 Bing bing bing bingbingbingbing *bingbingbing*
@MatthewAndThings
@MatthewAndThings 5 жыл бұрын
This channel is great, you explain things very clearly
@Kreeshawn
@Kreeshawn 5 ай бұрын
Wharf Rat is my favorite Grateful Dead song! Can't believe that got a shoutout haha, great video as always Kane. I watched a video recently about this topic and was ecstatic to find you had covered the topic
@philbelanger2
@philbelanger2 8 жыл бұрын
these would make perfect podcasts.
@tylerhulsey982
@tylerhulsey982 Жыл бұрын
Wasn’t expecting Wharf Rat reference. Terrific song. Poignant. “But I’ll get back on my feet someday…”
@justus4684
@justus4684 2 жыл бұрын
3:08 * V sauce theme starts playing *
@the3pista1c
@the3pista1c 11 ай бұрын
You say that this isn't an epistemological argument, but the central argument is that one cannot differentiate between a function like "plus" and "quus"; it questions how one can know which function they are expressing with the symbol "+". To say that it's a "deeper question about meaning" assumes that one can ask this question without appeals to lack of knowledge, which is obviously not true.
@KaneB
@KaneB 11 ай бұрын
The conclusion of the argument is not simply that we can't know whether we mean plus or quus, it is that there is no fact of the matter whether we mean plus or quus. That is the sense in which it isn't an epistemological argument. Now, maybe you don't think that the argument successfully establishes this conclusion. But that's what the conclusion is.
@the3pista1c
@the3pista1c 11 ай бұрын
@@KaneB Alright, but it seems that Kripke is purposefully defining "quus" in such a way that it eludes human knowledge (an equation you've never seen before, a new number never counted before etc.) so that there being no "fact of the matter" is still dependent on epistemological grounds
@Ansatz66
@Ansatz66 8 жыл бұрын
Surely objection 3 is the correct approach. Meaning is just the rules that we apply to understand the words that people say, and the words we say are tools that humanity has developed over the centuries to allow us to communicate. So to ask why some word has some meaning is to ask why we chose to give that meaning to the word when we invented it. Whenever we are looking for a reason behind a choice, we are looking for the mental state that caused the choice. Beyond that we may look for the situation that caused the mental state, but the mental state itself is the first step. We shouldn't take "mental image" too literally. Not every word is going to have a meaning that can be represented by a literal picture, but every word that you can understand must have a corresponding state in your mind that allows you to understand it. "If meanings are inner mental states, how can we ever share meanings?" The only way for us to share meanings is for our mental states to happen to coincide. Since we cannot view each other's mental states, there is no way to make this happen. This is made clear whenever people struggle to understand each other; one person cannot give her meaning for a word to another person. Instead we can only hint at the meanings of words by using more words and hoping to find some common ground. We write dictionaries in an effort to clarify the meaning of each word, but the exercise is entirely circular since each definition is given by nothing but other words. It is entirely possible that your understanding of the words you use is very different from the understanding of anyone you talk to. You may have failed to notice this because the misunderstanding very rarely has any noticeable consequences, just as you'd never notice the difference between plus and quus if you only dealt with numbers below 57. One day you may find a topic of conversation that exposes the differences between your meanings for words and other people's meanings, and then you will be totally bewildered. If our mental states do happen to coincide and we do actually share the meanings for the words we use, then surely that should be attributed to our shared humanity. We were all born and raised as babies listening to our parents speak and thus we all share a certain nature and a certain type of education, and so that may have lead us to a common understanding of the words we've learned. Objection 6 is also correct in a way, since words are constructed tools and their meanings are socially chosen, there is no deep explanation for why a word has a certain meaning. We could endlessly study the circumstances that lead to that choice, but there will never be a fully satisfactory answer since no one can ever really say why a choice like that was made one way rather than another way. In most circumstances it is probably best to just assume that meaning is a brute fact. It is like asking why Bob prefers chocolate over vanilla; in practice there is no answer, though we could spend lifetimes studying the brain and the chemistry of flavors.
@KaneB
@KaneB 8 жыл бұрын
+Ansatz66 Solution 3 and solution 6 are incompatible. Solution 3 takes meanings to be reducible to mental states; solution 6 is that meanings are irreducible.
@Ansatz66
@Ansatz66 8 жыл бұрын
Kane B "Solution 3 and solution 6 are incompatible." That's just a matter of perspective. Solution 6 is correct because meanings are axiomatic and axioms are irreducible, but looking at it in another way we can ask why we have these axioms instead of some other axioms. That leads us to the choices of people and mental states, so solution 3 is also correct. It's just that solution 3 is correct in a different way than solution 6. It depends on what sort of answers we're looking for. When something is arbitrarily chosen, it is fair to say that there is no reason for it and so it is basic. But from the perspective of a psychologist we can always dig deeper to discover what was going on in the mind of the person making the choice. Depending on how far you want to look, there are two answers that are each correct in its own way.
@KaneB
@KaneB 8 жыл бұрын
+Ansatz66 If meanings are mental entities they're not irreducible. I just don't see any room for debate about that. Solution 6 explicitly says that meanings are *not* mental states. Meanings are just meanings - they are not anything else.
@Ansatz66
@Ansatz66 8 жыл бұрын
Kane B "Solution 6 explicitly says that meanings are not mental states." Consider another case where there are two distinct correct answers depending on your perspective. Is Sherlock Holmes a detective? On one hand the answer is obviously yes, perhaps the most famous detective ever. I don't want to say that's wrong because from a certain perspective it is surely true, but on the other hand Sherlock Holmes is a fictional character and so he cannot participate in actual detective work and so he is not a detective. The people who say that Sherlock Holmes is a detective might tend to favor solution 6 because they are looking at things from an idealistic perspective. In the same way that Sherlock Holmes is a detective, meanings are basic since when we invented meanings we did not base them in anything. We just choose meanings arbitrarily. The people who say that Sherlock Holmes is not a detective might tend to favor solution 3 because they recognize that Sherlock Holmes is an idea rather than a person, and so Sherlock Holmes is a mental state in exactly the same way that meanings are mental states. Neither one of these approaches is really wrong. There's only a conflict if we don't recognize that they are coming at the question from entirely different directions. It is important to recognize that two people can see the same question in two different ways.
@KaneB
@KaneB 8 жыл бұрын
+Ansatz66 I don't really understand how the Sherlock Holmes relates to this, to be honest. I disagree with your analysis of it though. I would say that "Sherlock Holmes is a detective" is true in most contexts, because we can treat it as an abbreviation of "according to the stories by Arthur Conan Doyle, Sherlock Holmes is a detective". Without that qualification, it's not true whatever your perspective is. Solution 6 rules out solution 3. They cannot both be true, unless you want to defend some sort of ontological relativism. But in that case, all of the solutions can be true and all of the solutions can be false, it just depends on your perspective. I'm not a relativist. Meanings are either mental states or they aren't. If they are, then they are reducible, and so solution 6 is ruled out. The fact that people can see the same question in different ways doesn't change that. (Actually, I suppose you could hold that some meanings are reducible to mental states and some other meanings are irreducible. That would be a coherent combination of solutions 3 and 6. That doesn't seem to be what you're saying though - you seem to be suggesting that solutions 3 and 6 might be applicable to the very same meaning. That's not coherent.)
@leafsleafs2267
@leafsleafs2267 6 жыл бұрын
Blowing my mind
@ianhruday9584
@ianhruday9584 8 жыл бұрын
Maybe I didn't understand option 3, the mental content approach. Why is mental content equated with image? It seems clear to me that many of my thoughts are not images, but linguistic constructs. It's also pretty clear that the "addition of extremely large numbers" objection relies on our having numbers so large we cannot comprehend them. No deviant operator can be used for these numbers, because the numbers themselves cannot be understood.
@KaneB
@KaneB 8 жыл бұрын
+Ian Hruday I didn't mean to equate it with images. I do also talk about "thoughts" and "mental states" and "mental entities". I focus on mental *images* because I think that's the best way to illustrate the point (and it's what Kripke focuses on), but Kripke would argue that the same objections apply to any mental content. Let's say that the meaning of "plus" is given by some sort of "linguistic construct". I'm not entirely clear what a linguistic construct is, but I assume that it's something like a "word in the head". Now, just as an image in the head is not sufficient for meaning, how can a word in the head be sufficient for meaning? A word, like an image, is just a symbol whose meaning needs to be fixed. "It's also pretty clear that the "addition of extremely large numbers" objection relies on our having numbers so large we cannot comprehend them. No deviant operator can be used for these numbers, because the numbers themselves cannot be understood." I'm unsure what your point is here. It seems to me perfectly sensible to define a deviant operator for very large numbers (e.g. "glus - same as plus unless either number is higher than Graham's Number, in which case 5" - what's wrong with that?) Indeed, "plus" is defined for an infinite range of numbers. It would be an extremely radical kind of mathematical constructivism that rejects numbers that are very, very large. Perhaps I am misunderstanding you.
@ianhruday9584
@ianhruday9584 8 жыл бұрын
+Kane B Thanks. I misunderstood the mental states option. I have since re watched the video. re Large numbers: My objection here is that when faced with large numbers we have no disposition because the numbers are too large to understand. That its almost like being given no numbers at all. If I put the symbol + between two nonsense words, I would also not be inclined to return an answer. However, you suggested a alternate operator which would return 5 for sums of numbers which = larger numbers than we can comprehend. Since this was a criticism directed at the dispositional account, I have to ask "do you have the disposition to return 5 when faced with large sums?" If not then we can conclude on the disposition account that no deviant operators exist for very large sums. I also have a few thoughts about this question. Let me know if they make sense: philosophy of language is one of my weaker areas. 1. Although, it is difficult to evaluate counter-factuals for the ability to do sums all the way up to infinity, we can imagine being a little better at addition. So suppose you can do addition all the way up to some large number L. Well you can imagine being just a little more competent so that you can do sums all the way up to L + 1, L + 2, L+ 3... all the way to L+ L. Therefore, we can understand quite a few counter-factuals in which we have improved arithmetical capabilities. I'm not sure if this is enough since it is possible to construct new operators where our conter-factuals run out. 2. The skepticism about meaning seems to rely on a principle like: "if you cannot distinguish between two alternatives, then you cannot know which one is correct." He's saying "if you cannot tell the difference between quus and plus, then you cannot know which function is intended by the symbol "+."" So he's taking a Cartesian skepticism and turning it into skepticism about meaning. Is this a fair reading? I think there are two points here. 1st If the Cartesian principle doesn't hold then the argument fails. 2nd Even if it holds and we do not always know what we mean, it does not follow that there are no facts about meaning at all. For instance, even if I don't know if "+" means "plus" or "quus," that doesn't mean I don't know that "+" does not mean "-" or "pancakes." 3. It seems that there is a fundamental difference between the questions "what do I mean?" and "what does she mean?" For the first question I'm tempted to pull a G.E. Moor shift and say that I know what I mean even if I cannot prove it. For the second question I think a neurological explanation may be required.
@KaneB
@KaneB 8 жыл бұрын
+Ian Hruday "If not then we can conclude on the disposition account that no deviant operators exist for very large sums" Wouldn't that also rule out "plus" as well though? If you can't have the disposition to return "5" for Graham's Number + Graham's Number, you surely can't have the disposition to return the sum of it. "Even if it holds and we do not always know what we mean, it does not follow that there are no facts about meaning at all. For instance, even if I don't know if "+" means "plus" or "quus," that doesn't mean I don't know that "+" does not mean "-" or "pancakes."" I agree that this is something of a gap in Kripkenstein's argument. I don't know whether I mean plus or quus - but surely "pancakes" makes no sense at all. However, if we can't distinguish between "plus" and "quus", we can't know whether we should respond "125" and "5". Now, clearly, the argument can be generalized. So consider the rule: when presented with "x + y", answer with the sum of x and y unless either number is over 57, in which case answer "cletus awreetus awrightus" Or: when presented with "x + y", answer with the sum of x and y unless the date is after September 2016, in which case answer "cletus awreetus awrightus" So this is how meanings in general are undermined - we can generalize the argument so that it's completely indeterminate how we should respond to anything. "It seems that there is a fundamental difference between the questions "what do I mean?" and "what does she mean?" For the first question I'm tempted to pull a G.E. Moor shift and say that I know what I mean even if I cannot prove it. For the second question I think a neurological explanation may be required." This would be plausible if meanings are fundamentally and completely private, so that your meanings are not directly accessible to others. However I think most philosophers treat meanings as public, intersubjective phenomena, and would say that there can be a difference between what you intend to mean and what you actually mean. So it is in principle possible, and probably not uncommon in practice, that I could know the meaning of your utterances better than I know the meaning of my own utterances. The primary technical arguments for this view of meaning are probably Wittgensteinian "private language" type arguments. But there's also a more common sense argument. Suppose I utter "my friend Frank loves beech trees." Now, I don't know anything about beech trees. I wouldn't be able to distinguish a beech tree from any other kind of tree. If we treat meanings are totally private and subjective, then it looks like we have to say that my utterance is meaningless. Or at least, "beech tree" doesn't mean anything more than just "tree". But this is surely absurd. (And perhaps this is another problem with the appeal to mental states. It looks like my utterance means more than what can be determined by my mental states alone.)
@ianhruday9584
@ianhruday9584 8 жыл бұрын
+Kane B Thank you for your detailed response. I see how the point generalizes. Let me push back on a few points. First, I don't think the argument generalizes so easily. It may show that some meanings are partially undetermined, but I don't think it shows that they are completely undetermined. The argument you went over in the video seems to grant that we do know the sums of numbers from 1-57. It is only when we move past 57+57 that we run into deviant operators. The point is that this argument doesn't generalize to meanings in contexts we have used. re private meanings: Secondly, I do think its plausible to say that the phrase "Frank likes beach trees," can be meaningless if I don't understand what "beach trees" are. There is a broader point here, which is that words mean things TO people. I.e. meanings in language seem to be parasitic on meanings in the head. . However, there is a third problem with the arguments. If I understand the argument correctly he moves from the fact I don't know what I mean to the conclusion that there are no meaning facts. However, this only works if meanings are private. If meanings are public then the fact I don't know if I'm using the rule correctly cannot establish that there is no rule.
@KaneB
@KaneB 8 жыл бұрын
+Ian Hruday "Secondly, I do think its plausible to say that the phrase "Frank likes beach trees," can be meaningless if I don't understand what "beach trees" are. There is a broader point here, which is that words mean things TO people. I.e. meanings in language seem to be parasitic on meanings in the head" Surely "Frank love beech trees" *communicates* something more than just "Frank loves a certain type of tree", even though the latter is all that is given by my mental states. So if the point of postulating meanings is to explain language and communication, then it looks like meanings are intersubjective. I mean, sure, we can define meanings so that they are some special set of mental states. But what would be the point of such a definition? "If I understand the argument correctly he moves from the fact I don't know what I mean to the conclusion that there are no meaning facts. However, this only works if meanings are private. If meanings are public then the fact I don't know if I'm using the rule correctly cannot establish that there is no rule." Perhaps I should have made this clearer in the video, but Kripke is imagining a situation where we have unlimited epistemic access to potential meaning-determining facts. It's difficult to see how we could actually have perfect knowledge of our own dispositions, for instance (we often make incorrect predictions about our own behaviour). But Kripke's point is that even if we did know everything about our own dispositions, that still wouldn't tell us the meanings of our words. So, dispositions don't determine meanings. I think that the slide from "I don't know what I mean" to "there are no meaning facts" is legitimate if we assume unlimited knowledge.
@kurothi
@kurothi 8 жыл бұрын
Hi, Kane B. I'm loving your video and I have a question. Do you intend to continue philosophy of math? Is it complete or you just didn't want to do it anymore? If you actually stopped, could you recommend a nice introductory book about different views on math (platonism, etc)? Thank you very much.
@KaneB
@KaneB 8 жыл бұрын
+Thiago Mota "Do you intend to continue philosophy of math?" Not at the moment. It's not complete, but I became interested in other things. "could you recommend a nice introductory book about different views on math (platonism, etc)?" Introducing Philosophy of Mathematics by Michele Friend is a very accessible book that covers all the traditional views. For more contemporary debates, An Introduction to Philosophy of Mathematics by Mark Colyvan is quite nice.
@kurothi
@kurothi 8 жыл бұрын
Thank you very much! Your channel rocks!
@rath60
@rath60 Жыл бұрын
Can't we require meanings to be agreed upon by a pair of interlocutores. After all when I don't know the mesning of a word I ask someone else what it means. The if I agree with them we can use the word between unyil a conflict arises at wjich point we discuss the mesning and return to an agreement. Let us take jack and jill. Jack has onlh added number smaller thsn 57 and jill believes addition to be sinomis eith cus(c+). Jack ask jill what is 57 add 1. Jill answers 5. Jack enters into conflict he observes a add b must be greater than a and b. Jack suggest 63. Jill says well you might mean plus where S(a+b)=a+S(b) and a+0=a . So 57+1= 57+S(0)=S(57+0)=S(57)=58. Jack acepts Jill's conclusion. Until they disagree in the future. 0 is prior and S(0) in A and n in A implies the S(n) in A. A is the natural numbers.
@JohnSmith-rz7fh
@JohnSmith-rz7fh Жыл бұрын
It seems as if I’m 6 years late to the party, but I did have a comment to throw out here (I didn’t finish the video yet so it is possible that this is later addressed) and I’m hoping you could clear this up a few things for me. The whole dilemma presented seems to be a bit trivial and I’m not exactly sure why solution two doesn’t work. The question simply boils down to how do you know the plus symbol (+) carries out the function of addition rather than some other arbitrary function after a specific threshold is reached. I guess the answer in the real world would be that the (+) symbol universally refers to the function of addition and nothing else. In terms of the thought experiment given, the answer would be that the function of addition (naively speaking) doesn’t have an upper bound. Meaning that when we speak of addition, we speak in terms of abstract elements being added together, not specific individual numbers. So when defining addition, we would use an abstract notation such as (x + y) instead of something like (5 + 6), though it seems as if this is already assumed in your video. What I don’t seem to be understanding is, if we _do_ agree that addition is simply a function that can be applied (naively of course) to any two numerical elements _and_ that it _is_ an abstract process, I do not see why the example of adding two numbers larger than you ever added in the past would fall prey to this dilemma that you are proposing (which honestly seems like some sort of problem of induction). To give a more concrete example, let us use the numbers you provided, 57 and 68. Assume that, like you stated in solution 2, that there is a defined process (which is, in essence, what a function is) in producing the sum. Now, given that we know how to add anything under 57, this example should allow for me to know how to add numbers less than 10 (including 10). With that, the following can be given: In the case of (x + y) where x or y consists of two digits or more, the “carry rule” is implemented. Seeing that we both know what he carry rule is and how it works, there doesn’t seem to be the need for me to elucidate any further in terms of the proposed process. Now, from what I understand, the objection posed to this “process” solution would be “how do you know this process applies to numbers you’ve never added before?”, where the answer to that would be that the process isn’t “bound” in any sense, it applies to _all_ elements, regardless of the level of my prior exposure to them in an “addition” setting, which is why the abstract notation of (x + y) is given. Hence, irrespective of whether or not I have added any two numbers together, the application of the process follows by definition. Yet for some reason I feel as if I am rambling on like an idiot and actually missing what the dilemma you posed is, as this seems grossly obvious. I also had a gut feeling that it was possible that you were simply asking (although in a convoluted manner), “If (+) can mean addition and it can mean quus, how do you know which one it is?”. Now if this is the question, then I can see the dilemma, and one would be inclined to answer that you can’t. A tempting answer would be that you could _if_ what is meant by (+) is delineated before it is used, by saying that “(+) here is referring to addition”, though this doesn’t quite work. You see, _if_ the symbol (+) can have an arbitrary function meant by it, which seems to be obvious, then why couldn’t that apply to the words delineating it in this case also? Of course one could attempt to get around this by claiming some words’ definitions follow _necessarily_ , though this seems to be obviously false. I have a feeling this second description is far less trivial and closer to the dilemma you were attempting to illustrate than what I objected to earlier, though I still do not see the relevance of using the thought experiment of adding two numbers you’ve never added before as a didactic example. Hopefully you can clarify my confusions, thank you for the great work!
@MrNikeNicke
@MrNikeNicke Ай бұрын
"Seeing that we both know what the carry rule is and how it works" if this was true then solution two would work. This, however, assumes "the carry rule" has a definite meaning, the objection isn't “how do you know this process applies to numbers you’ve never added before?” but rather "how do you know what the process is?"
@JohnSmith-rz7fh
@JohnSmith-rz7fh Ай бұрын
@@MrNikeNicke The answer to such a question is simple, we _define_ the process and do so rigorously. If the process is defined, then I see no issue other than the second issue that I posited.
@MrNikeNicke
@MrNikeNicke Ай бұрын
@@JohnSmith-rz7fh it may just be the same argument as your second description, but the claim as I understand it is that there is no definition rigorous enough so that you cannot find some part of it and give two different accounts consistent with previous usage of what it would do in a novel case
@thisismyname9569
@thisismyname9569 7 жыл бұрын
The sum of "57+68" and the meaning(s) of "57+68" are not the same thing.
@MrAdamo
@MrAdamo 10 ай бұрын
4:19 AMONG US!!!!
@Min-zo8vu
@Min-zo8vu 10 ай бұрын
Sus!
@kyzercube
@kyzercube 8 жыл бұрын
quus appears to be a function while plus is just an operator. I've never heard of quus before, but it's pretty obvious that it is NOT an operator.
@KaneB
@KaneB 8 жыл бұрын
+kyzercube I don't think that this poses any problems for Kripke's argument. Just change it to "how do you know you mean the plus operator rather than the quus function?"
@kyzercube
@kyzercube 8 жыл бұрын
Kane B The problem of symbolic context is common everywhere when doing enough mathematics, especially calculus. It just seems like the problem presented in this video is nothing more than an old wine bottle with a new label. The number one problem with things like calculus AND from my personal experience, high level programming, is understanding the dialect of the programmer's methods of programming. You can write out the same equation and the same functionality of a program many many different ways. It's up to the reader to understand the dialect. In summary, all I'm trying to point out is that this Kripke's Argument is a moot point.
@androshchukx
@androshchukx 5 жыл бұрын
it is _fog_ that makes any meaning real/tangible, yet not exactly _clear..._ But _clarity/satisfaction/meaning_ is what is sacrificed in order to have reality(that may not make sense(be meaningfull), but is tangible/real for that reason...) Thus there is no "The Answer"... apart from illusion we can lust after/through by rubbing layer after layer of fog indefinitely... That is lust. (because the "correct" answer will always have it's opposite) But the real "solution" does not depend on the aid of memory... (it goes beyond knowledge...) not only making us eternal, but also making our bad/good memories invalid... (because all meaning becomes ambiguous) This is the art of detachment, through the sacrifice of meaning. But this does not mean you do not care... (but it seems that way...) you cannot fog anything up _too_ much.
@John-lf3xf
@John-lf3xf 2 жыл бұрын
Just because meaning is not definable does not mean it does not exist.
@radojevici
@radojevici 2 жыл бұрын
It's not the point that it doesn't exist or that it isn't definable, but that there is no fact of the matter whether something has one meaning or another
@John-lf3xf
@John-lf3xf 2 жыл бұрын
@@radojevici Yes there is simply because it is not definable or expressive doesn’t mean it doesn’t have a particular (at least probabilistically) absolute meaning.
@thenkindler001
@thenkindler001 7 жыл бұрын
Solution: reduce everything to probability. We can just agree that there is no certainty about whether we are plussing or quassing (nothing is certain when we introduce infinity) but that there is a high probability (this can be arbitrarily stipulated as 99.9999999%, which is satisfactorily accurate) that we mean plussing instead of quassing because most humans believe that they are plussing.
@radojevici
@radojevici 2 жыл бұрын
but there still is no fact of the matter to which you would attribute probability
@andrewsh7954
@andrewsh7954 7 жыл бұрын
Kripkenstein's approach is all over the place. He uses the word 'plus' and the symbol '+' in setting up the 'problem' but hasn't defined the terms. He accepts the day to day meaning and then claims that we could all be misinterpreting the terms and should actually apply 'quus' and its symbol. Quus is then defined in terms of addition implicitly as it uses the symbol '+' in the definition of Quus. Any mathematician worth their salt would first go to Peano's axioms and mechanically derive what any addition is. This does not rely upon a childlike definition of counting. The notion of slipping in to the conversation deviant alternate meanings, without justification, would be seen in other contexts as dishonest. Quus (A,B) = A+B if A+B = 125. In this case , using Kripkenstein's method we could subvert Quus and say , "oh no,, there is a deviant interpretation of Quss called Puss etc etc. The introduction of deviant interpretations gets you nowhere fast. Which does not imply that '+' has no meaning. Unfortunately this kind of claptrap gives philosophy a bad name. As Wittgenstein said, "I can think of no real problem that philosophy can or has solved". You can all see why he thought that and how wrong he was. (By solve I do not mean "definitive solution")
Kripke's Meaning Skepticism 2 - The Skeptical Solution
32:10
Wittgenstein and the Rule Following Paradox
21:19
Attic Philosophy
Рет қаралды 5 М.
Happy birthday to you by Tsuriki Show
00:12
Tsuriki Show
Рет қаралды 11 МЛН
Cute kitty gadgets 💛
00:24
TheSoul Music Family
Рет қаралды 12 МЛН
Bony Just Wants To Take A Shower #animation
00:10
GREEN MAX
Рет қаралды 7 МЛН
这三姐弟太会藏了!#小丑#天使#路飞#家庭#搞笑
00:24
家庭搞笑日记
Рет қаралды 52 МЛН
Kripke's Meaning Skepticism 3 - A Straight Solution
35:00
Kane B
Рет қаралды 3,1 М.
Kripke on Rigid Designators
48:52
Daniel Bonevac
Рет қаралды 12 М.
Gottlob Frege: Sense and Reference Explained
14:11
Absolute Philosophy
Рет қаралды 32 М.
What is meaning? - Verificationism
45:14
Kane B
Рет қаралды 9 М.
Noam Chomsky - Language and Thought
4:49
Chomsky's Philosophy
Рет қаралды 136 М.
Kripke
44:27
Daniel Bonevac
Рет қаралды 59 М.
Kripkenstein! (The Rule Following Paradox)
12:27
Carneades.org
Рет қаралды 22 М.
Kripke on Wittgenstein on Forms of Life
45:58
Daniel Bonevac
Рет қаралды 12 М.
Noam Chomsky on Bertrand Russell
1:36
Chomsky's Philosophy
Рет қаралды 177 М.
Happy birthday to you by Tsuriki Show
00:12
Tsuriki Show
Рет қаралды 11 МЛН